The Social Contract
“Since no man has a natural authority over his fellow, and force creates no right, we are left with agreements as the basis for all legitimate authority among men.” Jean-Jacques Rousseau – The Social Contract
The theory
of contractarianism can be found mainly in the works of Thomas Hobbes, Jean-Jacques
Rousseau, John Locke, and Immanuel Kant. I will focus here on the theories of
Hobbes and Rousseau in order to unpack what is the social contract and how this
links to theories of Natural Law, the State’s legitimacy, how it requires
consent as its basis, and whether this social contract actually exists.
HOBBES
The political
philosopher Thomas Hobbes, who lived in the sixteenth century, accepted the
philosophical argument of the day that a person’s highest duty was
self-preservation. Therefore, according to Hobbes, the state of nature is a
condition of perpetual turmoil between disconnected, competing individuals. It
makes sense that the state of nature was for him a state of war, as the highest
duty was not morality, but precisely the lack thereof: purely animalistic
survival. Hobbes focused on the selfishness and
competition between men because he was describing the bourgeois man of an
emerging capitalist society and stripping off him any type of civilisation. It
is wrong, some argue, to depict men before civilisation as purely self-interested
and antisocial, as nature provides multiple examples in which it behaves in a
cooperative and harmonic manner. If, on the contrary, one perceives the nature
of men to be also a moral and cooperative one, the (state) Leviathan does not
seem a viable means for peace but one of submission in which freedom is effectively
taken away from people. This counter-argument depends then on the evidence
found in pre-historic communities for example, it could not be based on, as
Macpherson rightly proposes, an extraction of the main traits of men who are
already used to living in a highly competitive industrialised world. And even
in those, there are multiple examples of cooperation amongst men. Moreover,
without those, no civilisation would stand the test of time.
According to Hobbes,
the ‘self-preservation instinct’ is responsible for both social scenarios: war
and harmony. This survival instinct drives men to take from others whilst
creating ‘a war of all against all’; however, it also drives them to cooperate
with one another by agreeing in a common coercive power. Consequently, there
arises a contract between rational beings in order to keep peace and preserve
one’s life; it is a purely economic exchange of which we can all theoretically
benefit.
A ‘covenant of every
man with every man, in such manner as if every man should say to every man, I
authorise and give up my right of governing myself, to this man or to this
assembly of men’ (Hobbes, 2014:134).
Hobbes clearly started
from the assumption that 1) morality is something that emerges after we are out
of that state of nature, with the association; and 2) the right of governing
oneself not only leads to state of war but has to be given up in order to get
into the contract with others.
The idea that there is
no morality before the contract has the implication that each contract keeps
changing and evolving as morality is created with it and vice versa, as it
annuls the idea that there are overarching laws or principles by which we are
all governed, leaving it to the sovereign to decide. But this is moralrelativism at its highest since when morality is placed on one person alone, it
loses its meaning. There is an overarching morality and it can be discovered but
it does not depend on one sovereign and it is discovered by all of us individually
and within ourselves only. Therefore, we reach an important question, is man
only free when he is chained in order to suppress his inner selfish desire? Or
can men transcend or transmute that selfish desire and turn their existence
into a moral one?
The covenant emerges
then when one knows that everybody else has done the same, leaving like that
the ‘monopoly of force’ to the state. It is, therefore, argued by Hobbes that the
lesser opinions on how to defend the country, the lesser division on how to
proceed. In this unified and single-headed form of government, internal
conflict is reduced and ‘peace’ takes place. Hobbes was clearly advocating for
an absolute sovereign that could not be questioned nor challenged by the common
man. A contracting man exchanged his natural rights for protection and security
but he preserved the right of self-defence because without it the contract
would not make any rational sense and because, according to Hobbes, that right
does not pose a challenge to society’s peace. Consequently, the attainment of
peace demands that no one “resists the sword of the commonwealth in defence of
another man” (Leviathan, 169); prohibiting like that collective resistance.
ROUSSEAU
Rousseau’s
thought was quite the opposite to Hobbes’. They both started from different
premises about the nature of man. In the state of nature, people were
completely free but, instead of Hobbes’ state of war, Rousseau thought that people
lived in abundance because of their simple lives. As civilisation developed and
populations increased, men had to share nature with a lot more people and there
was competition between us. People became inextricably interdependent and with
that came the separation of labour and the distinction between social classes,
what degenerated in chaos and conflict. Therefore, Rousseau’s assertion that “men
are born free but they are everywhere in chains” expresses this evolution from
natural freedom to civilised slavery.
The
philosopher thought that for society to function there would need to be laws to
keep peace and harmony. But if the sovereign holds absolute power, that would
soon be to the detriment of the people and their natural rights, thus rendering
the contract useless for those people. If the ones making the laws are the same
ones in power, it is highly likely that they will pass laws to favour their own
interests instead of the interests of the whole. We can already see that the
main consequence of starting out from different premises on the state of nature
is where will we find morality to be located. According to Rousseau, exchanging
survival for protection removes all kind of morality from people’s actions. He
writes:
To renounce your liberty is to renounce your status as
a man, your rights as a human being, and even your duties as a human being.
There can’t be any way of compensating someone who gives up everything. Such a
renunciation is incompatible with man’s nature; to remove all freedom from his
will is to remove all morality from his actions. (The Social Contract, 4)
Subjecting the will of the
self to the community’s will is dangerous precisely because we would be starting
off by subjected and not free individuals and… can individual slaves compose a
free collective? I’d say quite the opposite, only free individuals can make up
a free society. This is, in my opinion, a crucial flaw with contractarianism. If
morality is not prior to the collective (or any type of) contract, there can be
no freedom. Freedom and slavery are both manifested within and without oneself,
and individuals enslaved by their own passions, fears, desires, etc,. can never
produce freedom outside themselves, not to mention create a free collective.
To say that a man gives himself to someone else, i.e.
hands himself over free, is to say something absurd and inconceivable; such an
act is null and illegitimate, simply because the man who does it is out of his
mind. To say the same of a whole people is to suppose a people of madmen; and
madness doesn’t create any right. (The Social Contract, 14)
Rousseau was, therefore,
disposed to find a formula for a form of association that allowed individuals
to maintain their natural rights and thus be free, while uniting with other men
with the purpose of protecting their goods and mainly those same rights. This
would be a way to maintain the social order while avoiding doing so by force.
He writes: "the social order isn’t to be understood in terms of force; it
is a sacred right on which all other rights are based. But it doesn’t come from
nature, so it must be based on agreements." This is so because if we understand
nature as everything, we would have to include the possibility of erring, of doing
wrong, and that disturbs the social order. Man is the only creature that has the
option to choose whether to do good or evil. So, it is an individual choice
that stems out of the individual’s free-will what allows the social order or
what disturbs it. And this, paradoxically, is what I call Natural Law, it is
the ability of men to understand and subject themselves to the natural forces
governing this world and to choose the right path. The social order therefore arises
out of each individual’s agreements with others; as disagreements will provoke social
chaos. This polarity is found everywhere in nature. But the social contract
varies from tribe to tribe, from town to town, from state to state as it is
based on customary understandings of right and wrong.
We can see there that the covenant
is not natural, it arises out of the free will of each individual man, and
because of that, it can be dissolved. The choice is morality, and that is
natural, the outcome of that is man-made and thus it starts being a mirror-like
version of nature which has its time and place but which has an expiration date;
as further away it gets from nature closer it gets to deteriorate and finally
disappear. But men seem to have a hard time with the idea that nature is
cyclical, that there is life and death constantly everywhere one looks. Death
is just a part of life, the matter decomposes and it serves for the soil to be able
to grow new life. These are the patterns we see everywhere and, although men try
to go against it, it is a real law and cannot be broken. Anything we do that
goes against nature is doomed to fail. Rousseau claims that:
In order “to protect the social compact from being a mere empty formula, it
silently includes the undertaking that anyone who refuses to obey the general
will is to be compelled to do so by the whole body. This single item in the
compact can give power to all the other items. It means nothing less than that
each individual will be forced to be free.” (The Social Contract, 8)
This oxymoron
presents perfectly the main problem with the social contract theory. If one is
born into imposed man-made unnatural rules, those are going to be necessarily in
contradiction with those natural laws and our nature as natural creatures, and that
is something that we cannot avoid even if we tried to. So, we are forced because
this contract is done when we are babies and when we do not object or work in
order to change the social contract in adulthood. It is never a consented contract,
and so it is neither an agreement, because we are born into it and we are “forced”
to be part of it. The best representation of this is the birth certificate, as
it is the bond that is created by the state that keeps us in bondage with the
collective “public”. The idea that what we are unwillingly signing up for is “to
be free” would highly depend on what we mean by freedom. For Rousseau, as
opposed to Hobbes, the requirement that individuals governed themselves was crucial
if those were going to have to willingly enter into the agreement. And however idyllic
direct democracy sounds when reading Rousseau, history shows us that the collective
can be far more dangerous as people are indeed subjecting their responsibility
to govern themselves to the collective imaginary governing them.
It is
forced precisely because, at the micro level, I cannot bind you into an
agreement with someone else; either you enter into the agreement yourself
willingly or it, by definition, is not an agreement. So, at the collective
level, the state cannot force anyone to enter into a contract, it can also not force
the social contract onto free beings. That is why the state creates the “creatures
of state” which are called persons and which are subject to codes, statutes and
regulations. These are entities which are effectively slaves and which work for
the state. Because they are mere abstractions, the state has power and control
over them. No fiction can have control over natural men, but fiction can have
control over its franchised fictions. Therefore, as long as natural men
identify with the fiction and allow themselves to be subjected to the will of
the state (or sovereign), it is a consented contract and it falls under the
category of a seemingly “valid” social contract. But if men discover that they
are free and that they have always been and that they can free themselves from
the will of the collective by simply stop identifying with the fictional entity
and start taking responsibility for themselves and thus stop needing the state
to act as a father for them, then they shall be free from the agreement-bondage
made upon them by their forefathers.
If one thinks about the
social contract in those terms, it makes much more sense. People who are not
willing to take liability for themselves can keep being chained to the state’s
privileges and duties as good citizens. Those who wish to live their own lives
according to higher laws above men have to undergo a process of understanding,
meditating, cultivating, etc… A process of working on their fears, their
conceptions of love and right and wrong and like that to be able to break free
within and thus without too. These beings will not pose a threat to the peace
of society because they have understood why those mechanisms are there, how men
can actually become a wolf to men, as Hobbes would say, and with that knowledge
collaborate on the collective growth instead of the collective destruction.
Maxim of Law:
Non videntur qui errant consentire.
He who errs is not considered as consenting.
Contract Case Law:
"Every mean is independent of all laws except those prescribed by nature. He is not bound by any institution formed by his fellow men without his consent" Cruden v. Neale ZNC 338 May Term (1796)
"Failure to reveal the material facts of a license or any agreement is immediate grounds for estoppel" Lo Bue v. Porazzo, 48 Cal.App.2nd 82, 119, p.2d 346, 348.
"Waivers of fundamental Rights must be knowing, intentional, and voluntary acts, done with sufficient awareness of the relevant circumstances and likely consequences." U.S. v. Brady, 397 U.S. 742 at 748 (1970); U.S. v. O'Dell, 160 F2d 304 (6th Cir. 1947)"
Unconsciable "contract" - "One which no sensible man not under delusion, or duress, or in distress would make, and such as no honest and fair man would accept." Franklin Fire Ins. Co. v. Noll, 115 Ind. App. 289, 58 N.E. 2d 947, 949, 950.
"Party cannot be bound by contract that he has not made or authorised" Alexander v. Bosworth (1915), 26 C.A. 589, 599, 147 P.607.
The fraudulently "presumed" quasi-contractus that binds the Declarant with the CITY/STATE agency, is void for fraud ab initio, since the de facto CITY/STATE cannot produce the material fact (consideration inducement) or the jurisdictional clause (who is subject to said statute).
"The term "liberty" ... denotes not merely freedom from bodily restraint but also the right of the individual to contract to engage in any of the common occupations of life, to aquire useful knowledge, to marry, to establish a home and bring up children, to worship God according to the dictates of his own conscience… The established doctrine is that this liberty may not be interfered with, under guise of protecting public interest, by legislative action." Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.S. 390, 399, 400.
"The right to be let alone is the most comprehensive of rights and the right most valued by civilised men. To protect that right, every unjustifiable intrusion by the government upon the privacy of the individual, whatever the means employed, must ne deemed a violation of the Fourth Amendment" Olmstead v. U.S., 277 U.S. 438, 478 (1928).
"Both parties to a contract must agree to its terms and to be bound in legal relations. The corollary of that is that one person cannot unilaterally impose a contract on another." Silver's Garage Ltd. v. Bridgewater (Town), (1970) CanLll 196 (SCC)
Comments
Post a Comment